4 Discussing Scientific Consensus on Climate Change

Matthew Silk

What information must news organizations and scientific communities share?

Stakeholder Map Prompt: Using the instructions from “How to Create and Use a Stakeholder Map,” create a stakeholder map in your notes, either individually or with your class. Show the topic, the subjects affected, and possible outcomes based on the ideas introduced at the beginning of this article and your own background knowledge of the topic.

 

Concerns about the climate are becoming more pronounced in politics and policy discussions with each passing year. In a 2019 E.U. election, Green parties witnessed a marked increase in support. In Canada, the Green Party recently doubled their national caucus and managed to come second in a provincial election. In the U.S., there is hope of a Green New Deal. However, the federal administration in the U.S. has issued new directives to various national agencies to strip references to climate change or to omit worst-case scenarios. Public debates and media coverage emphasize the near-universal consensus of climate scientists, but, on specific issues, this level of consensus simply does not exist. The nature of scientific consensus on the issue of climate change makes public discussion difficult, and this has ethical implications for how the public should be educated on matters of science.

Studies show that the American public tends to believe that the consensus on climate change is around 72%, while many in the media (John Oliver’s Last Week Tonight being a good example) focus on the point that 97% of climate scientists agree on the issue of human-caused climate change. Getting the public to understand the degree of scientific consensus is important; it allows the public to be better able to address the dangers of climate change and assess the merits of various policy proposals. However, an important issue that is often not discussed is what exactly is meant by “scientific agreement.” The degree of scientific consensus isn’t constant as projections differ substantially. While there may be a risk in underemphasizing the degree of current consensus, there may also be a risk in overemphasizing it as well. Is it worth potentially muddying the waters by attempting to have a more complex and nuanced public discussion about the nature of this consensus and the implications of climate change?

The issue of scientific consensus is more complicated than it is often described in public discussion. Researchers are beginning to warn policymakers about the extreme possibilities of climate change that are downplayed or excluded for the sake of presenting a united front. While there is broad agreement between climate scientists regarding humans’ impact, views quickly diverge when considering the finer details. This disagreement leads many reports to minimize uncertainty by excluding less understood (but significant) processes. Because of this, various models may be subject to a “premature consensus.” On topics ranging from future changes to precipitation, only half of scientists find a common ground on which they can agree.

Given the seriousness of global climate change, it is obviously beneficial that the public takes the threat seriously and that they are confident in what scientists are telling us. No doubt this is why the “97% consensus” point is so compelling. But emphasizing consensus at the expense of considered disagreement and uncertainty comes with risks. This is important knowledge for policy debates; the public has a vested interest in knowing if official projections are under- or overestimating the potential harm. This may be especially important at the local and regional level since, for example, coastal regions are likely to be disproportionately affected by the effects of climate change. Vigorous public input in these regions may be not only desirable but necessary.

Appreciation of scientific consensus is important for depoliticizing the facts around climate change. But the more the details and limitations of this consensus are discussed, the greater the risk that the facts become politicized by a public who may not have the time or expertise necessary to process the information. Is it worth it then to have the public be informed about disagreement when there is concern that the consensus view may underestimate projections about extreme events? More specifically, is it worth it if the result is that in the public eye scientific consensus is weaker than originally thought and ultimately less is done about climate change overall? Even if there is broad consensus on the notion of human-caused climate change, climate change deniers would likely seize the opportunity to use reports of disagreement to undermine intervention efforts.

Deliberately refusing to publicize instances of climate scientists’ disagreement makes for a less informed public and we generally consider this a bad thing. It can undermine public trust in science and in the public’s ability to make well informed democratic decisions. However, if there is greater coverage of scientific disagreement the facts might easily become twisted. If public confidence in scientific consensus falls, people will be more inclined to adopt skeptical beliefs.

These questions pose an important moral challenge to both producers and consumers of news. Perhaps the long-term answer is to focus on science education, but that can take time. Plato’s Republic advocated for a “noble lie” in order to ensure social cohesion and harmony. Reporting only on consensus and glossing over areas of disagreement may constitute a lie of omission, but is it noble to do so?

Respond to the following questions in your notes and through classroom discussion.
  1. Is it morally permissible to strategically select what climate change information to share with the public, or are we morally obligated to share all information come what may? Who should have the final say in making that decision?
  2. We often object to misinformation campaigns on the grounds that they rob their victims of the opportunity to exercise autonomous choice. So why not think that by limiting the possibility for spin we are simply restoring this basic power to individuals? Isn’t there a difference between actively distorting facts and passively omitting unnecessary details?
  3. Given the public’s inability to appreciate the details of climate science, why should we think it’s necessary to share that information in the first place? When, if ever, might the details we share exceed our obligation and become too much information?

 

Share This Book